[page 17, §1]
[17.2.1] Already at the beginning of calculus one of its founding fathers,
namely G.W. Leibniz, investigated fractional derivatives
[73, 72].
[17.2.2] Differentiation, denoted as (
),
obeys Leibniz’ product rule
![]() |
(2.1) |
for integer ,
and Leibniz was intrigued
by the analogy with the binomial theorem
![]() |
(2.2) |
where he uses the notation instead of
to emphasize the formal operational analogy.
[17.3.1] Moving from integer to noninteger powers Leibniz suggests
that "on peut exprimer par une serie infinie une grandeur comme"
(with
).
[17.3.2] As his first step he tests the idea of such a generalized
differential quantity
against the rules of his calculus.
[17.3.3] In his calculus the differential relation
implies
and
.
[17.3.4] One has, therefore, also
and
generally
.
[17.3.5] Regarding
with noninteger
as a fractional differential
relation subject to the rules of his calculus,
however, leads to a paradox.
[17.3.6] Explicitly, he finds (for
)
![]() |
(2.3) |
where was used.
[17.3.7] Many decades had to pass before Leibniz’ paradox was fully resolved.
[page 18, §1]
[18.1.1] Derivatives of noninteger (fractional) order
motivated Euler to introduce
the Gamma function [25].
[18.1.2] Euler knew that he needed to generalize (or interpolate, as he calls it)
the product to noninteger values of
,
and he proposed an integral
![]() |
(2.4) |
for this purpose.
[18.1.3] In §27-29 of [25] he immediately applies this formula
to partially resolve Leibniz’ paradox,
and in §28 he gives the basic fractional derivative
(reproduced here in modern notation with )
![]() |
(2.5) |
valid for integer and for noninteger .
[18.2.1] Generalizing eq. (2.5) to all functions that can be expanded into a power series might seem a natural step, but this "natural" definition of fractional derivatives does not really resolve Leibniz’ paradox. [18.2.2] Leibniz had implicitly assumed the rule
![]() |
(2.6) |
by demanding for integer
.
[18.2.3] One might therefore take eq. (2.6) instead of
eq. (2.5)
as an equally "natural" starting point (this was
later done by Liouville
in [76, p.3, eq. (1)]), and
define fractional derivatives as
![]() |
(2.7) |
for functions representable as exponential series
.
[18.2.4] Regarding the integral (a Laplace integral)
![]() |
(2.8) |
as a sum of exponentials, Liouville [76, p.7] then applied eq. (2.6) inside the integral to find
![]() |
(2.9) |
[page 19, §0]
where the last equality follows by substituting
in the integral.
[19.0.1] If this equation is formally generalized to
,
disregarding existence of the integral, one finds
![]() |
(2.10) |
a formula similar to, but different from eq. (2.5).
[19.0.2] Although eq. (2.10) agrees with eq. (2.5)
for integer it differs for noninteger
.
[19.0.3] More precisely, if
and
, then
![]() |
(2.11) |
revealing again an inconsistency between eq. (2.5) and eq. (2.10) (resp. (2.9)).
[19.1.1] Another way to see this inconsistency is to expand the exponential function into a power series, and to apply Euler’s rule, eq. (2.5), to it. [19.1.2] One finds (with obvious notation)
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
(2.12) |
and this shows that Euler’s rule (2.5)
is inconsistent with the Leibniz/Liouville rule (2.6).
[19.1.3] Similarly, Liouville found inconsistencies [75, p.95/96]
when calculating the fractional derivative of
based on the definition (2.7).
[19.2.1] A resolution of Leibniz’ paradox emerges when
eq. (2.5) and (2.6) are compared
for , and interpreted as integrals.
[19.2.2] Such an interpretation was already suggested
by Leibniz himself [73].
[19.2.3] More specifically, one has
![]() |
(2.13) |
showing that Euler’s fractional derivatives on the right hand side differs from Liouville’s and Leibniz’ idea on the left. [19.2.4] Similarly, eq. (2.5) corresponds to
![]() |
(2.14) |
[19.2.5] On the other hand, eq. (2.9) corresponds to
![]() |
(2.15) |
[page 20, §0] [20.0.1] This shows that Euler’s and Liouville’s definitions differ with respect to their limits of integration.
[20.1.1] It has already been mentioned that Liouville defined fractional derivatives using eq. (2.7) (see [76, p.3, eq.(1)]) as
![]() |
(2.7) |
for functions representable as a sum of exponentials
![]() |
(2.16) |
[20.1.2] Liouville seems not to have recognized the necessity
of limits of integration.
[20.1.3] From his definition (2.7)
he derives numerous integral and series representations.
[20.1.4] In particular, he finds the fractional integral
of order as
![]() |
(2.17) |
(see formula [A] on page 8 of [76, p.8]). [20.1.5] Liouville then gives formula [B] for fractional differentiation on page 10 of [76] as
![]() |
(2.18) |
where .
[20.1.6] Liouville restricts the discussion to functions
represented by exponential series with
so that
.
[20.1.7] Liouville also expands the coefficients
in
(2.7) into binomial series
![]() |
![]() |
(2.19a) | |
![]() |
(2.19b) |
and inserts the expansion into his defintion (2.7) to arrive at formulae that contain the representation of integer order derivatives as limits of difference quotients (see [75, p.106ff]). [20.1.8] The results may be written as
![]() |
![]() |
(2.20a) | |
![]() |
(2.20b) |
[page 21, §0]
where the binomial coefficient is
.
[21.0.1] Later, this idea was taken up by Grünwald [34],
who defined fractional derivatives as limits
of generalized difference quotients.
[21.1.1] Fourier[29] suggested to define fractional derivatives by generalizing the formula for trigonometric functions,
![]() |
(2.21) |
from to
.
[21.1.2] Again, this is not unique because the generalization
![]() |
(2.22) |
is also possible.
[21.2.1] Grünwald wanted to free the definition of fractional derivatives from a special form of the function. [21.2.2] He emphasized that fractional derivatives are integroderivatives, and established for the first time general fractional derivative operators. [21.2.3] His calculus is based on limits of difference quotients. [21.2.4] He studies the difference quotients [34, p.444]
![]() |
(2.23) |
with and calls
![]() |
(2.24) |
the -th differential quotient taken over the straight line
from
to
[34, p.452].
[21.2.5] The title of his work emphasizes the need to
introduce limits of integration into the concept
of differentiation.
[21.2.6] His ideas were soon elaborated upon
by Letnikov (see [99])and
applied to differential equations
by Most [89].
[21.3.1] Riemann, like Grünwald, attempts to define fractional
differentiation for general classes of functions.
[21.3.2] Riemann defines the -th differential quotient of a function
as the coeffcient of
in the expansion
of
into integer
[page 22, §0]
powers of [96, p.354].
[22.0.1] He then generalizes this definition to noninteger powers, and
demands that
![]() |
(2.25) |
holds for .
[22.0.2] The factor
is determined such that
holds, and found to be
.
[22.0.3] Riemann then derives the integral representation [96, p.363]
for negative
![]() |
(2.26) |
where are finite constants.
[22.0.4] He then extends the result to nonnegative
by writing
"für einen Werth von
aber, der
ist,
bezeichnet
dasjenige, was aus
(wo
) durch
-malige Differentiation nach
hervorgeht,…"
[96, p.341].
[22.0.5] The combination of Liouville’s and Grünwald’s pioneering
work with this idea has become the definition of the
Riemann-Liouville fractional
derivatives (see Section 2.2.2.1 below).